Ella: Dworkin on Semantic Textualism and Scalia's View of The Sixth Amendment

On page 43, Scalia brings up his disagreement with the Court’s decision to allow a child victim of sexual abuse to testify with on the prosecutor and defense counsel present. Scalia dissented this decision because it violated the Sixth Amendment which holds the right for the accused to be confronted with the witness against him. 


I agree that the Court’s decision here was inconsistent with the meaning of the words of the text. However, Scalia’s basis for this argument ends up being quite weak. He goes on to say that “one of the major purposes of that provision was: to induce precisely that pressure upon the witness” (44), so as to put pressure on the accuser to not lie. He drives his point home by saying that “the only significant that have changed, I think, are the society’s sensitivity to so-called psychic trauma.” Here is where my issue with Scalia’s argument lies—it is not necessarily a subjective social sensitivity that prompted the Court’s decision, but rather, new scientific evidence and understandings about the effects of child abuse, that may have coincidentally changed social sensitivities as well. 


What I am saying is in essence an agreement with Dworkin. Textualists should be afforded the ability to change their interpretations of the text to go beyond how the framers understood it, so long as they are semantically consistent. For example, as Dworkin points out on page 120, although the framers may not have thought capital punishment to be cruel and unusual, it is now, by modern standards, considered cruel and statistically unusual. It is not that the method of interpretation of the words has changed, but rather that the evidence and information with which the words are interpreted has changed. The definition of cruel and unusual has not changed, only what is understood to be considered cruel and unusual in modern society. Much like how the definition of the Fourteenth Amendment was not changed due to a new interpretation in Brown v. Board. Rather, the information used to interpret that statute (which demonstrated that separate is in fact not equal) was more expansive. 


My argument against Scalia’s dissent of the child abuse case differs from Dworkin’s points, however, because I am pointing out how Scalia’s dissent is inconsistent with his interpretation of the Sixth amendment rather than the words of the Sixth Amendment itself (this is in itself another issue, because Scalia is hypocritically invoking legislative intent to explain an amendment, but that is not the point of this blog post). I concede that the Court’s decision went against the words of the Sixth Amendment, but it did not go against the intention of the Sixth Amendment. With the information we have on abuse now, it can be understood that putting an abused child before their abuser (who likely manipulated them) may make them more inclined to lie on the abuser’s behalf. Therefore, forcing a child to testify in front of their abuser would not ensure the intent of the Sixth Amendment like Scalia claims. This is a conclusion that has not changed the meaning of the Sixth Amendment’s purpose. Rather, it is a change in the understanding of how to implement the Sixth Amendment’s purpose.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

Livia: Táíwò and Economic Success in the Global South

Carlos: Response to Henry's Conclusion

Smith, Locke, Harris, and Justice